All Research is Research
Creation
(suggested music while
reading - Was (Not Was)’s Wheel Me Out)
All research is research- creation, even if some research
pretends otherwise. All research is necessarily, if at some times more weakly
than others, an assemblage to produce the new. What masks this is that much of
the new is “preterritorialised” in matrices of standardisation, from performance outcomes
to the necessity for a press release telling the world of the immediate utility
of an innovation.
All research is
research-creation because everything really is relative - although not in the
lazy manner that many silly caricatures of cultural theory (such as Sokal and
Bricmont’s) often suggest. Gilles Deleuze writes that this is “not the
relativism we take for granted. It is not a variation of truth according to the
subject, but the conditions in which the truth of a variation appears to the
subject” (1993: 20). This truth of a variation is what is discovered by research-creation.
Understood this way, all research is research-creation because the real, if you
like empirical, world is constantly re-assembling itself, in process. This has
been noted by philosophers from Alfred North Whitehead to Gilbert Simondon,
Isabelle Stengers and Gilles Deleuze and Fèlix Guattari. As Brian Massumi
notes, even ‘change changes’ (2002: 10).
At the same time, even
though all research is research-creation, to create the new with awareness that
this is what we are doing makes all the difference in the world. All research
is research-creation but not all research-creation is the same.
Worlding
(suggested music while
reading - Cinematic Orchestra’s Breathe)
Research-creation does not
mimic biblical creation. It is not so much an engagement between us on the one
hand and the world on the other. It is more a matter of what Massumi calls
‘worlding’. Here “the self-network is a worlding of the human” (Massumi 2002:
128). There is an ongoing mix of relations between habits, perceptions and the
movement of our specific ecological contexts. To create the new is to
participate in worlding differently.
Here also we can understand
the technics - by which I mean simply technologies and techniques - that are
crucial to the activity of research-creation. In worlding -
[…] subject and object
integrate into a greater autonomy of participation, a matter-manner meld adding
a new line of multiple-singular encounter to the world: that of a technic, an
artificed between of any number of possible subjects and objects, autonomous of
any given particular subject or object. (Massumi 1997: 755)
Worlding with awareness is
made possible by the refusal - a technically orchestrated refusal - of the
world to be owned, by legal deed, by concept, or by experimental design. To
research is to focus, then, on how participation occurs. This is again a
question of technics. Technics describes the partial, always incomplete attempt
at what used to be thought of as agency (now agency as participation and
becoming) within worlding.
Technically then, the
question is not one of whether we should have research-creation or not, but of
what kind of research-creation we are able to have. There can be little doubt
that much research is pushed - particularly by institutions which are
constantly reconstituted by a certain mode of technics of discipline or control
- towards what I am calling here preterritorialisation. This is the attempt to
standardise and recuperate research into a certain order before it occurs, even
if in terms of a standard deviation or pre-fixed range of variations or
possible modulations. This attempt at order is doomed in absolute terms (after
all, change changes), although technics is all about the extent to which such a
doom can be postponed.
Technics’ freedom to impose
a certain temporary order in the face of this doom tell us that order of a kind
is possible - that a semblance of order can be found. However, the fact that
technics can rework the order of things freely also tells us that there is no natural sovereignty or
hierarchy to forms of knowing. Neither are disciplines nor faculties given (whether in the university
or the brain/mind). It was certainly never a given that there were C. P. Snow’s
famous ‘two cultures’ of science (knowing/research) and art (creation),
although it is just as certain that there has never been one, but many
cultures. Any order within this - even an order of preterritorialised variation -
within forms of knowing has to be constantly recreated immanently ... and
technically.
[1]
For all these reasons, creation is often folded into
institutionalised research in a particular manner, the more so as creativity
becomes an industry. Martin Heidegger’s description of research as ‘ongoing
activity’ (1996:53) remains apposite. For Heidegger, the ongoing activity of
research attempts to confirm a certain ‘world picture’ - aligned with certain
disciplines and faculties. More importantly, the very idea of affirming a
complete and stable world as picture - as being able to be represented - becomes
the central aim of research. It is important to note again that even here such
research is not uncreative or even closed in any absolute sense. Heidegger’s
term ‘ongoing activity’ reflects this.
Given a world in which
everything is creation, ongoing activity assembles events as best it can within
the terms of an impossible closure. To some extent we are all wrestling with
this impossible closure. Today, however, a series of new technics are emerging
in research creation that challenge this world picturing, its ongoing activity.
These technics explore questions such as the new relations between imagination
and reason that might be possible, or new faculties of knowing or thinking.
What follows is a series of idiosyncratic sketches - often, as we shall see,
involving dogs as research collaborators - of both impossibly closed and impossibly open research creation.
We Are All Scientists, We
Are All Artists
(suggested music while
reading - Joni Mitchell’s Refuge of the Road)
A final note before these
sketches. Although research-creation often feels dramatically experimental
- and is genuinely exciting - it is not unusual. Not only is all research
research-creation but research-creation is a common cultural condition, even if
traditional institutions sometimes pretend otherwise. We are all both scientists
and artists - inevitably exploring in our everyday life both our technical
limits (science) and our own impossibilities of closure (art). Just as
importantly, we are all increasingly immersed in the bigger pictures of science
and art as these two dramatically reconfigure their relations, often with us as their laboratory. Better
known examples might be the dramatic increase in the use of pharmaceutical
products targeting the brain, basic self-improvement or performance management,
or the regulation of teaching and learning via technics of
preterritorialisation (defining learning outcomes and aligning these with
assessment, learning activities, and constrained forms of student feedback, all of these
in turn feeding into performance management). These situations - in which it
becomes harder to picture a stable world - suggest that we are truly situated in a
worlding of shifting self-network relations (not always of the most ethical
sort), more than a world picture. This is not only by virtue of what is
almost a command to take up ongoing activity, as both scientists and artists. We
are also immersed as subjects in a series of ongoing experiments (whether by
the World Bank or global warming) that the Futurists themselves could not have
dreamed of. So the stakes involved
in thinking through research-creation are very high.
Tommy’s Pause
(suggested music while
reading - Colleen’s Ritournelle)
Tommy - the border collie,
Labrador cross in this picture - is, like all dogs, a natural and radical
empiricist. He is thoroughly and unashamedly focused on the relational. For
example, one of his things is to lie down with his paw over your foot as you sit on
a chair, often licking both paw and foot together so you can’t tell which is
which. He is of course incomprehensible in his relatedness. Yet he demands to
be thought with. It’s in his eager gaze.
It’s a strange thing to look
an animal in the eye and have it look back at you and think (although one will
never know what). It happened to me once with a polar bear in Copenhagen Zoo.
We looked at each other from a metre and a half away, although separated by two
rows of thick steel bars. It happens too with Tommy. I remember one time in
particular, just playing, yet one which both Tommy’s owner and I still remember years
after. Tommy loves repetition and difference in that dog way that turns simple
repetition into an ongoing relation. Once when he was half-grown, we played
endless chasings around a pillar in the centre of the house. The best part for
Tommy seemed to be the moment when he paused on the other side of the column,
looked around the corner at me, and waited for something in my eyes to give
away the direction in which I’d try to catch him. This was a pause of pure relationality
- no pretence at preemption or outcomes. Yet it also felt like the most agency
one will ever get (that is, partial, incomplete, totally immersed in
relations). Not just becoming-dog; becoming-chasings.
As dogs seem to understand,
such moments - extended by repetition and difference into durations, can be a becoming-technics
or a technical evolution of relations. Technics builds on the simple
differential repetition involved in relationality, with all technics emerging
from a re-assemblage, a resynthesis in contemplation, of other technics of relation- not only more formal
technics, but less formal, such as chasings, or the famous fort/da of Freud.
These simple technics can return to serious research in a productively
disruptive way, as when children and animals are allowed into the room where serious discussion is occurring, a
common occurrence in many of the most intellectually produced research
workshops with which I have been involved. These technics are not always grand.
They are in fact often trivial, everyday. They also leak into other experiences. They
add to the complexity of research events by breaking up
hierarchies. For
example we could take, in The Sense Lab’s Dancing the Virtual workshop in Montréal in
2006, the leakage of experience between the
simplicity of relational
movement exercises led by Erin Manning and the philosophical discussion.
Relational movement, in this workshop at least a kind of contact improvisation
for beginners, involves a kind of initiation (re-assemblage) into a technics of
relation common to dancers. It involves - at least at the beginning - simple
experiences such as placing a hand on another’s chest and then moving with each other without this
involving pushing or pulling. An
impossible closure. An impossible opening. Constraint and opening in a simple
yet extreme form. Such relational movement is not open to debate. It is working
or not - and you know immediately which. This had a profound effect on the
direct philosophical discussion, which was conducted with precision at an
extremely high level, but with no expressed animosity - of the kind usual in so
many academic contexts - for three days. I think this was at least in part
because the relational movement re-assembled things at a deep level, or rather
re-assembled things so that they focused on the immanent condition of relations
rather than on their preterritorialisations. In turn, there were successful
attempts to do philosophy - research-creation. ‘Create a movement of thought!’ was
one command that worked. These still resonate, and will carry through to
further workshops in the series (and others as the technics developed are both
cloned and mutated elsewhere).
Maybe this is what happens
if you let dancers into the room with philosophers.
I will write more about dogs
and empiricism below, but for now I’ll note that some of the workshops I’ve
been to that worked best in terms of opening out to a radical empiricism were those in which animals
(usually dogs, but also sometimes cats, or even kangaroos or kookaburras in
Australia, the latter of which have a laugh which is an instant call to radical
empiricism) wandered through, and often children as well. All these carry their
own leaky radical empiricisms - their percepts, their affects, their creation
of concepts.
They even work with their
own radical empiricist scientific functions, described by Deleuze and Guattari as
‘a fantastic slowing down’ by which ‘matter, as well as the scientific thought
able to penetrate it with propositions, is actualized’ (1994: 118).
It is of course said that
one should ‘Never work with children and animals’. Why? They’re unpredictable. They don’t follow the script.
Put a dog or a child on stage and they will explore it for what it is, not what
it represents - or perhaps freeze, not having been habituated to performing
their part but aware that something is demanded – a script must be followed.
For the radical empiricist, however, it’s the script that, while often
enabling, needs to be departed from. This is in fact a purer empiricism as
nothing, not even habit, sticks to the script, even in the most rigorous
repetition.
Clone Your Technics
(suggested music while
reading - Keith Fullerton Whitman’s Stereo Music for Yamaha Disklavier Prototype, Electric Guitar and
Computer)
Whenever I have told others about
experiences such as Dancing
the Virtual or the Biophilosophy and the Politics of Life event run in Australia in 2003 by the
Humanities Research Centre (in which much of the discussion took place on a
farm by the ocean, with animals and children as part of the event), a first
question has been ‘but what did you do’ - and then, ‘how do you do this kind of
thing?’.
These questions are neither
utopian nor romantic. They are technical. They are also not obscure questions,
for academics only, but concern modes of experimental development in everyday
relations as much as in special workshops and conferences (just as traditional,
hierarchical forms of research, including conference organisation, reflect a
broader cultural technics of knowledge production and impact).
‘How do you do it?’ It has
also been my first question when hearing of other events that are attempting
new forms of research-creation, such as the Freecooperation event organised by Trebor
Scholz and Geert Lovink at Buffalo in 2004.
[2]
‘How do you do it?’ has a
simple practical answer. Tell people what works - technically. Clone your
technics. Make copies. Distribute them. Make them available to others on the
web (make an interpersonal equivalent of BitTorrent for research-creation
technics, learn from the Open Source community). It’s like giving cuttings of
plants to others for their garden. It’s actually hard to begin to understand
research of any kind until you’ve done it - especially its precise technical
limitations and possibilities. Moreover, although we are not the first to
experiment - there have always been radical empiricists, and a radically
empiricist mode of living - we are only now perhaps developing and popularising
the vocabulary, the concepts, the technics. It’s often hard to explain exactly
the vocabulary, the concepts. However, technics are something that can be
easily communicated, experienced.
Christophe Spehr’s three
rules for free cooperation are a case in point. They are meant to be cloned.
They are limits or functions, scientific in that they actualize - slow things
down - in a certain manner. Yet they are also enabling in that they are a
technics of limitation that bring a basic constituent of research-creation into
being - namely free cooperation itself. Spehr’s rules are -
first ... that all rules in
this cooperation can be questioned by everybody, there are no holy rules that
people cannot question or reject or bargain and negotiate about - which is not
the case in most of the cooperations and organizational forms that we know. ...
second ... that people can
question and change these rules by using this primary material force of
refusing to cooperate, by restricting their cooperation, by holding back what
they do for these cooperations, making conditions under which they are willing
to cooperate, or leaving cooperations.
...
third ... which is important
because otherwise it would be just a blackmailing of the less powerful ones by
the more powerful ones - is that the price of not cooperating, the price that
it costs if you restrict your cooperation or if the cooperation splits up,
should be …not exactly equal …but similar for all participants in this
cooperation, and it should be affordable. That means, it can be done, it's not
impossible, it's not a question of sheer existence to cooperate in this way.
(Spher)
These rules dismantle
hierarchies immanently, or allow for this. Yet they need to be strict to do so.
To repeat, it is important that this recipe is a certain set of enabling
limitations - that even when everything goes, not everything goes.
It is just as important to
see that this recipe for creating the new is not the only one. Yet the more
general character of enabling limitation is probably something shared by most
research-creation technics.
Habit As Enemy and As Friend
(suggested music while
reading - whatever you don’t normally listen to)
Such technics standardise
repetition in terms of experience, but only so as to change things (one obvious
example is cooking - we measure ingredients, oven temperature, etc, so as to
change eggs, flour and sugar into a cake). It would be tempting to oppose this
technics to another - which changes things in order to standardise them, to
bring them back into standardisation, but this would assume that an order of
bare repetition - of standardisation - was possible. If so, it would look like
Matthew Fuller’s ‘standard objects’ (for example, shipping containers). Even
here, however, the point is that these allow for a “mobilization of affordances
within them, drives that surpass their limits” (Fuller:169).
Standardization does not
guard against change because, famously, as described in Deleuze’s Difference
and Repetition,
repetition and difference are mutually involved. For Deleuze, difference is not
a difference between objects, but a difference over the time of the repetition,
in duration, the new intensity of flows that shipping containers make possible,
for example (the difference container shipping keeps making to the world). Such
forms of differential repetition supplement the human in order to express the
human in interaction with other forms of supplementation, of rocks, of animals,
of climate (think here of the shipping of King Kong from a remote island to
New York perhaps). In supplementing the human, the technics of differential
repetition also define the human, and thus Deleuze and Guattari’s
‘mechanosphere’ (1987: 514) or Bernard Stiegler’s understanding of technics
(1998).
The human feels these
ecologies of differential repetition and supplementation as habit, and habit is
in some ways the very substance of research-creation.
One of the first
counter-intuitive ideas in Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition is that repetition in
itself inevitably opens to difference. This is because it is in repetition that
we contract events into a sensed duration. It is this which enabled us to feel
differential movement (in the martial arts or dance, for example, two
repetitions of established sequences of movement feel simultaneously related
and always different). This contraction - as habit - is fundamentally enabling.
In Deleuze’s view, habit is never a matter of ‘just repeating’ things as they
were. It is rather a matter of creating the smallest durations between one
instance and another in order both to repeat and to differ. Habit - even within
one’s own isolated experience - is therefore always relational. We are not just
our relations with others. We are quite literally made up of relations to ourselves -
shifting differential durations - through time. Even if we can clone our
technics - our modes of repetition - we can never clone our selves.
Habit is the embodied mode
of differential repetition. It is true that changing habits is one of the main
technical aims of research-creation. However, it is also true that habits are
necessarily temporal formations of possibility for change. They are the friends
as well as the enemies of research-creation. This is because habits are the
friends of time, and time is the friend of research-creation.
Still, there are habit and
habits. If habits are the very substance of research-creation, the urgency of
research creation concerns which way these habits are tending to take us. A
radical empiricism
that does not only begin with relations but accepts that we are not just analysing
them,
making them the basis for a new kind of taxonomy of experience, but that we are
remaking relations - changing our habits, and our institutions as collective
habits - as we go.
We need to think about cloning
our technics then, in terms of the way that this cloning fosters an awareness/experience of
difference within research creation. First, this is not only a question of a
morphogenetic variation but a variation over time within the relations that
hold any form together. Second, with this more complex understanding of our
habits as a kind of basic series of techniques for holding our own difference
and repetition together, and our technics as a kind of ecological form of
difference and repetition, we can see technics in research creation as a way of
habitualising our existential ecologies differently, of finding the micro-forms
of living that can tolerate/work with impossible closure, impossible
openness.
Pragmaticism as Having Done
with the Judgment of God
(suggested music while
reading - Burial’s Ghost Hardware
Critique, in itself, does not give us these new forms of living.
In the context of radical empiricism, critique has ‘run out of steam’ as Bruno
Latour puts it. Or perhaps, in
Deleuze’s terms, critique is not harsh enough. A more radical critique, a total
critique, leaves nothing standing - except perhaps the relations with which to
begin creation. In either case, what does replace critique as usually
practiced? It begins with something like ‘immanent critique’, which, as Massumi
notes, asks of critics ‘that they actually take the risk of putting themselves
into play, accepting that they may exit the event having fundamentally changed’ (personal communication with The
Sense Lab).
This is to develop the habit
of changing habits, and to change habits is to change forms of embodiment (not
least to abandon the pointing of the finger fond of which critics are so often
fond).
Embodiment is a Founding
Assumption, not an End or Aim
(suggested music while
reading - Autolux’ Asleep at the Trigger)
Some caveats or principles
about where to start when working with embodiment. First, it's not a good idea
to insist that mind should be embodied, or that it should be taken as extended
throughout an ecology (that is, mind is ‘brain, body and world’, as Andy Clark
puts it). Mind already is both. Second, not only do we ‘not know what a body
can do’ - as Baruch Spinoza points
out - in theory – and we do not know what we might be able to do with body one
day. We
don't know what our bodies will do, in practice, from moment to moment (thus
another important aspect of questioning habit and the micro-constitution of
experience -keeping up with embodiment). We keep only a rough control -
sometimes like a sailing ship in a breeze, but sometimes also like the same
ship in a perfect storm. Third, it is not a question of whether we might take
the reality of the virtual into account (but in reality thinking this as too
difficult).
[3]
It is already taken into account by real events, and we must respond. This is
again a question of finding appropriate technics for research-creation, rather
than asking whether it is occurring. It is occurring all the time. We live
between the limits of constrained experiment and full creation - between
shifting relations and the new functions and limits they constantly provide and
to which we must adapt. We can easily trip over the body, if we are not careful
to acknowledge the multiplicity of virtual and actual relations in which it is
immersed. Fourth, research-creation, as in much of the hard sciences, is not
only about finding new words for things, in order to better represent them.
Rather, research-creation takes place over - and between - a wide range of
forms of expression. Fifth, research creation is not lacking in discipline.
Bodies need sometimes to be told what we think they can do, in order to find
out what else they can do. Sixth, bodies are relational ecologies. Mind is
assembled, in Gregory Bateson’s terms, as a series of ecologies.
Assembling Collective
Thought
(suggested music while
reading - September Collective’s Natura)
At the Dancing the
Virtual workshop, such ecologies were often brought into being via commands that were
both strict and open. As mentioned, one of these was ‘create a movement of
thought’.
Specific projects might
develop more specific commands/tasks. In the project Assemblage for
Collective Thought, begun in 2006 by Anna Munster and myself, and influenced by Dancing
the Virtual (and my case by previous collaborative work with Mat Wall-Smith), we set up
tasks in the form of commands that were specific but again open. These defined
the contribution of images, video, sound and text by participants (Dragana
Antic, Michele Barker, Gillian Fuller, Matthew Fuller, Lisa Gye, Ross Harley,
Brett Neilson, Anna Munster, Andrew Murphie, Kate Richards, Trebor Scholz and
Mat Wall-Smith). These contributions were mixed in a performance in San Jose in
September and it was allowed to anyone working on the ongoing project to remix
them.
Three of the tasks/commands were:
1. Return
to Nature
Task 1.
Collaborate with the natural world.
Find a
relationship in nature which assists you to produce thought, image, video or sound. Produce the text,
images, video or sound and leave them below.
Task 1.1
optional.
Become
either cellular or marine in your mode of collaborating.
2. Be
Passionate
Task 2. Be
passionate with another
Give vent
to any passion that was produced in relation to another living or nonliving thing. Leave your
response below.
Task 2.1
optional.
Make it
almost monochrome.
6. Conserve
the virtual
Task 6.
Make a contribution to virtual ecology
Do your bit
for conservation - make something that preserves or enriches our relations to the virtual. By
the virtual we mean
the real reservoir of relations between all
the different potentials in the assemblage.
Task 6.1
optional
in 3 seconds
The Mobility of Thought vs.
the Mobilization of Thought in Research Creation
Always it is a question of
going with the mobility of thought - with its habitual creation of new
relations over time as they shift. This mobility is very different to that labeled ‘mobilization’ by
Stengers (114), although of course
neither is static.
What Stengers calls ‘mobilization’ is now found in the arts and
social sciences as much as in the physical sciences, in art itself as much as
in science (even as the borders between all these blur). For Stengers, ‘mobilization’
accompanies the very real, experimental ‘proliferation of practices’ (114) in
all science. Because these practices inevitably depart from the old, a
‘mobilizing model’, along with a series of rhetorics, is designed to recapture
them. In ‘mobilization’ often a model (or series of models) is mobilized to
maintain ‘order in the ranks of researchers’ and ‘arm them against what would
otherwise disperse their efforts’. These models re-affirm certain disciplines
against that which escapes them. There is a price to pay. As Stengers asks,
‘what knowledges and practices will be destroyed, or prevented from being
invented, in the name of what must be called a “mobilizing belief” - namely,
the faith in a future where the body will show that its rational
representatives were indeed right? ...’
How do ‘rational
representatives’ arm themselves against what is also the necessary
proliferation of practices in all experimentation? There are many counter-technics involved - in what is
itself an experimental proliferation in reaction-creation. Many of these, such
as the scaffolding of experiment in discourses of defined outcomes and perhaps possible
impacts,
are preterritorialising. Others involve the posing of significance as a form of
disciplining moral and expert judgment, or even pseudo a priori technics such as the
imposition of bell curves.
The technical complexity of
much of this is relatively recent. However, it draws on the frantic vestiges of
1950s cognitivism, in which every proper thought had to be processed neatly and
cleanly, within a defined and knowable technical system that would tidy up the
performance not only of communication, but of thought itself. As new forms of
reaction-creation seem to overwhelm older institutions - as new technics begin
to be cloned - the way we think differently about the processes of thinking
will be crucial.
Thought and Radical
Empiricism
(suggested music while
listening - Loscil’s Cloister)
An overbearing and neat
cognitivism is not the only way to think about the relation between experiment
and thought. There are other ways to pose the relations between thinking
processes, and a radical empiricism that I have been suggesting here is
unavoidable (even though it takes more and less useful techno-social forms). It
is here useful to turn to the basics of William James’s discussion of radical
empiricism.
As it happens, James’
definitions of cognition and of radical empiricism are quite similar. About
cognition he writes -
the relations of continuous transition experienced are what make
our experience cognitive. In the simplest and completest cases the experiences
are cognitive of one another (James 1912: 87-88)
So cognition is not
primarily about the processing of symbolic representations, as in cognitivism,
as in much of popular culture discourse, political theory and practice, and
media’s representations of itself. In James’ work, cognition is rather about
the continuous experience of relations (experiences of transition are cognitive
of each other) as they shift.
To radical empiricism. This
is a “philosophy of pure experience” (James, 86), and experience here is of the
continuous transition of movement-matter. More than this, it is the relation of
one transition of movement-matter - involving brain, body and world - to other
transitions. This interwoven series of transitions produces shifting
intensities which in turn (recursively) produce transitions. Thus experience is
both of and via the ongoing (intensive) differential relations which for all
these philosophies make up the world. Put simply, “experience itself, taken at
large, can grow by its edges” and “life is in the transitions’”(James, 87).
Thus, James writes of his
philosophy of experience that there is “no bedding; it is as if the pieces
clung together by their edges, the transitions experience between them forming
their cement” (86). There is thus no permanent cognitive structure, of the
faculties for example.
This echoes Deleuze’s view,
in which Antonin Artaud overturns Kant’s assembling of the ‘Faculties’. Here
Deleuze writes of a -
[...] generalised thought process which can no longer be covered
by the reassuring dogmatic image [of a neat assemblage of thought processes, of common sense
]
but which, on the contrary, amounts to the complete destruction of that image
[...] henceforth, thought is also forced to think its central collapse, its
fracture, its own natural ‘powerlessness’ which is indistinguishable from its
greatest power - in other words,
from those unformulated processes […] Artaud pursues in this the terrible
revelation of a thought without image, and the conquest of a new principle which does not allow
itself to be represented [...] the difficulty [...] is not a de facto state of
affairs but a de jure structure of thought. (Deleuze, 1994: 147)
It is not states of affairs
that are the problem. It is the imposition of fixed arrangements - certain
technics - by which thought is considered to be thought. Thought is the
opposite to a fixed process or form of self-fulfilling recognition. The process or
aim - such as there is one - is creation. For Deleuze, ‘To think is to create -
there is no other creation - but to create is first of all to engender thinking within thought’ (1994:
147). In the process, given arrangements of thought are destroyed.
Each faculty must be borne
to the extreme point of its dissolution, at which it falls prey to triple
violence: the violence of that which forces it to be exercised, of that which
it is forced to grasp and that which it alone is able to grasp, yet also that
of the ungraspable (from the point of view of its empirical exercise).
(Deleuze, 1994: 143)
One can only understand the
aspects of thought we call faculties - or in fact any elements by which we
think we know, and therefore arrange, thought, from the point of view of their
destruction by their objects. Moreover, here “one cannot prejudge the outcome of
research’” (Deleuze, 1994: 143). Some well-known faculties may “turn out to
have no proper limit” (and can therefore never be understood, thus Jacques
Derrida’s ‘différance’ without limit). There may be “new faculties ... which
were repressed by … common sense” (Deleuze, 1994: 144). This is before we get
to the destruction of any image of thought, as per Deleuze’s Artaud.
We are now in a position to
understand James’ radical empiricism -
To be radical, an empiricism must neither admit into its
constructions any element that is not directly experienced, nor exclude from
them any element that is directly experienced. For such a philosophy, the
relations that connect experiences must themselves be experienced relations,
and any kind of relation experienced must be accounted as ‘real’ as anything
else in the system. (James: 42)
How is this different to ordinary
empiricism?
James goes on to note that ‘ordinary empiricism’ (42) - what I’ll call simply testing - ‘has always shown a
tendency to do away with the connections of things, and to insist most on the
disjunctions’ (43). James writes (and one sees clear links to Heidegger’s ‘Age
of the World Picture’):
The natural result of such a
world-picture has been the efforts of rationalism to correct its incoherencies
by the addition of transexperiential agents of unification, substances,
intellectual categories, or Selves .... (James: 43)
Tests as Transexperiential
Agents
It is stunning how many
proponents of strong theories of agency, of worthy individuals, and so on,
immediately delegate the determination of the degree of agency or worth to a
series of tests (of IQ, worthiness of citizenship). All of these are
transexperiential, and often abstract or reductive of experience.
To the categories of
‘transexperiential agents of unification’ that James lists we might then add models, especially
insofar as they inform practices of testing that validate or invalidate
experience.
The proliferation of
cognitive models and its related culture of testing - particularly since World
War II (Edwards, Dupuy) - have played a particularly important role in the
development of cultures of research. In the realm of the cognitive, unification
proceeds precisely via testing and correction, the more so that we now live in
an age of what Avital Ronell has recently called ‘The Test Drive’. In a reverse
mirror image (or not?) of research-creation, she describes the mood of culture
this way:
Whether you mean to prove
that you can do it, or we are driven by what Maurice Blanchot calls ‘the trial
of experience,’ and he submits himself endlessly to Nietzsche's loyalty tests,
or she is a runaway replicant whose human factor is being scrutinized, or the
sadistic coach has us revving up for an athletic contest; whether you are
entering college, studying law, or trying to get out of an institution; whether
they are giving you the third degree; whether you are buffing up on steroids,
or she had unprotected sex [...] it seems as though everything - nature, body, investment,
belief - has needed to be tested, including your love. What is the provenance
of this need to torture, to test? A link between torture and experiment has
been asserted ever since Francis Bacon; yet, what has allowed acts and idioms
of testing to top out as an essential and widening interest, as a nearly
unavoidable drive? (1)
One of the final tests of research-creation might
be whether it can depart from, or overturn from within, this test drive (is
there no outside to the test?).
In technical terms, radical
empiricism’s nemesis and the test drive’s topological foundation is the model -
or at least the model considered as disembodiment, decontextualisation of real
relations,
the admission of elements not directly experienced (IQ for example), the
exclusion of directly experienced relations. A consideration of the model
explains why radical empiricism might have particular relevance to cultural
theory now.
Models
(suggested music while
reading - Barbara Morgenstern’s The Operator)
‘Take me to the operator, I
want to ask some questions’
- Barbara Morgenstern, The Operator
Let’s start with a simple
question - what is a model? A model is often taken as a kind of map for process
in the world. As a technics however, it can be thought a little differently.
Models are diagrams that corral the forces of thinking processes. In corralling
thinking processes, models also provides the blueprint for a corralling of
other forces. This is often seen as a philosophical question. It is, however,
more crucially a question of everyday practice - in which whether models are
right or wrong is perhaps not as important as what they do with people in the
thick of directly experienced relations.
As I have suggested, a
crucial series of models is that involving thinking processes themselves.
Indeed, perhaps most basic models for Western culture are those of thinking
processes. It is via these models that thinking becomes cognition - and not only in theory.
Such models perform a kind of ‘brain-magic’ (Murphie, 2006) - a transformation of forces and relations.
[4]
Via the magic diagrams of models, thinking really does tend towards becoming cognition, technically speaking,
which is to say, in how it operates, what it does.
‘Symbolic Without Being
Fictitious’
How do models corral forces
of thinking in the move towards cognition (or elsewhere)? In large part this
occurs via a bringing together of a structure of signs. This is a question in
part of the reality of the virtual - that is to say of the power of structure
(Deleuze remarks here that the virtual - which is structure - is “symbolic
without being fictitious” [1994: 208]). This is to suggest that a sign itself
is also a kind of mini-model. As Massumi has remarked, signs themselves corral
differences and forces. “The presence of the sign is not an identity but an
envelope of difference, of a multiplicity of actions, materials, and levels”
(Massumi, 1992: 10). A sign is a kind of habit - a contraction of repetitions
that forms a duration - although this is a habit possessed by an entire
ecological context. Again, this is a matter not primarily of representation but
of bringing together “a multiplicity of actions, materials”. Seen as the habits
of an ecology, it can be understood why signs “animate behaviour” (Deleuze,
1994: 73). As Deleuze puts it – “The signs by which an animal senses
the presence of water do
not resemble the elements which its thirsty organism lacks ....” (ibid).
Signs are a question of how
experience of difference (between the element of the sign and the presence
of water for example) is contracted into relation and the consistency of a duration. For
Deleuze, this is an active contraction - or synthesis - which occurs more in
the contemplation of differences over time, than in direct action per se (which
is based only subsequently upon the synthesis involved in contemplation)
(Deleuze, 1994: 73). Thus the crucial nature of the contemplation of difference
- of the problematic task or demand - within research-creation. Of Tommy the
dog and I stopping to think in our game of chasings.
If signs create experience
out of difference, so much the more it is for models that bring signs together
into particular constellations.
From Experiment to Model
Models - and their
particular constellations of signs, habits, durations, we might even say the
particular conditioned reflexes they spread around, are often themselves
derived from experiment. Models arise from a bringing together of signs and
habits (including now the test as sub-model for action) formed in the laboratory. This laboratory can be an
actual lab, or everyday life considered as the site of experiment. Here we can
perhaps think of two kinds of cultural practices related to experiment, not
always as separate as they might seem.
The first of these cultural
practices related to experiment is one in which the sign - and, even more
effectively, the conjunction of signs known as the model - envelopes difference
in a totalising manner. To experiment here is to explore the new, but it is
also to bring it to order, usually via reductive practices. Difference is constrained in accord
with a constellation of previous model-practices in order to draw out a new
constraining model-practice. In the process, embodied behaviour - without which
we could not imagine models or any other kind of abstraction - is put on a
leash, as I hope to show shortly is precisely the case concerning Ivan Pavlov’s
dogs.
The second of these cultural
practices related to experiment is one that to some extent inverts the first,
or sometimes, if this is possible, simply ignores it. This is radical
empiricism - in which the reality of contingent experience, of relations, of
multiplicities, of encounters, is not corralled but taken into account.
Experiment here has a very different meaning in that it is relations,
contingent experience, that lead out of models.
The Obsession with Models -
Where Does it Come From? Pavlov’s dogs
(suggested music while
reading - Coldplay’s Green Eyes)
Jean-Pierre Dupuy, in his
book on the history of cognitive science, provides a wonderful example of a
model-obsessive:
Herbert Simon, winner of the Nobel Prize in economics, is
generally considered to be one of the founders of artificial intelligence [...
and] a sort of Leonardo da Vinci for our time […] the complete list of his
works includes Models of Man, Models of Discovery, Models of Thought, and Models of Bounded
Rationality.
The title of his recently published autobiography, Models of My Life
, hardly comes as a
surprise. (Dupuy: 27)
But here I want to go back
to way before artificial intelligence to document model-obsession, although
this is to a moment from which A.I. and cognitivism arose. It is the moment
that returns us to dogs, specifically the moment in which Pavlov harnessed them
in the laboratory.
Raymond Fancher has
described a disturbing and interesting phase in Pavlov’s experiments, when
things went wrong:
[...] breakdown in the dog’s
behaviour became known - perhaps misleadingly - as an experimental neurosis
[...] In one [experiment], a dog had been conditioned with great difficulty to
salivate when an electric shock to one of its rear feet was the conditioned
stimulus. Originally, the dog had responded to the shock by struggling in its
harness and trying to escape the situation. After many reinforcements with
food, however, it began to accept the shock calmly, and immediately began
salivating when it was administered. On the crucial trial, the shock was
applied to a different leg from that to which it had become accustomed. The
stimulus elicited a much stronger avoidance response than the animal had ever
shown before [...] All of the earlier conditioning disappeared, and the animal
required several months to recover from its neurosis. (Fancher: 307-8)
A vicious radical empiricism
perhaps, at the birth of a significant model of behaviour, which should perhaps
have warned us about what was to come in the test drive. It may seem strange to
ask, in this context, how Pavlov felt about his dogs - about the real relations
experienced. About what might have been gained - and lost - had his relations
to dogs, his own experience not been subordinated to the pursuit of the model
of the conditioned reflex. In fact, Pavlov was not insensitive to the suffering
involved. As Hilaire Cuny writes -
On a monument to the dogs
used in experiments [...] he had these words carved: ‘The dog, man’s helper and
friend from prehistoric times, may justly be offered as a sacrifice to science;
but let this always be done without unnecessary suffering.’ (Cuny:26)
Despite this sensitivity -
such as it is - I want to point out the obvious. The sign of Pavlov’s dog, and
the models associated with it, have had an enormous effect on cultural practice
(not least within educational and other performance cultures, although I am
certainly not suggesting that all of this has been negative). Constraint in
research-creation is a double-edged sword.
The effect of Pavlov’s dogs’
constraints has been precisely that of ‘an envelope of difference, of a
multiplicity of actions, materials, and levels’, via the many permutations of
behaviourism. I should mention in passing that, of course, there are many
alternatives to behaviourism as a model of thinking processes - notably
cognitivism and constructivism - but in many ways, the influence of Pavlov’s
dogs has been so great that these alternatives find it difficult to escape the
shadow of the dogs - their harnessing, their testing, their conditioning, their
reduction to more abstract diagrams and models, their experimental neurosis. Under the powerful magic
of a model such as Pavlov’s diagrammed dogs, alternatives can run the risk of
multiplying the impact of cognitive-behavioural models (which are now often
found together, as in CBT) on cultural practice. I also think it is Pavlov’s dogs
that very effectively demonstrate how models arise from embodied experience.
Abstracting the Harness
(suggested music while
reading - Gillian Welch’s The Devil Had a Hold of Me)
George Lakoff and Mark
Johnson’s theory of metaphor is useful here. For them metaphor is always an
abstraction - if initially a slight abstraction - that can only be meaningful
because we relate it to embodied experience that we ourselves have had. In
short, metaphors in everyday life are an example of how a kind of low-level radical
empiricism is turned into model. Simple examples are those of feeling up or feeling
down.
Pavlov’s dog works so well
as a model in part because we all have embodied experience of dogs.
Paul Edwards has given another significant example of this shift
from specific embodied experience to model: the specific problems of World War
II communications in the battlefield. This involves a highly specific embodied
context simply not relevant elsewhere - namely the urgency of getting a message
to someone else and the profound noise such a message was trying to get through
(imagine having to tell someone on a lower deck on ship to see and shoot down
an incoming plane). Yet this experience was to become generalised into the most
predominant model of communication - the Shannon-Weaver model. This is a model
that famously attempts to reduce noise in favour of clear, one-way linear
transmission of signal through a docile channel. This is, of course, very
sensible when trying to get a message through to a gunner - in the very noisy
situation of battle - to shoot down an incoming plane. Yet, thankfully, this is
not the situation we find ourselves in most of the time.
Despite this, the
Shannon-Weaver model is found everywhere today. For example, it is found, along
with various forms of cognitivism and behaviourism, in educational theory and
practices - and via educational theory it has come into research culture. The
contemporary university teacher is positioned as a docile channel between
performance systems as sender, and students as destination, or the researcher
as channel for the interests of stakeholders.
Let’s return to Pavlov’s
dogs. As with Shannon and Weaver, a particular embodied context, namely a dog
freely moving around, is not only reduced in its field of action (harnessed in
a lab).
[5]
It is then abstracted, reduced to this abstract. If you look for pictures of
Pavlov’s dog on the web, one of the first things you’ll find is that there are
few actual pictures, but many diagrams of the dog constrained within a little
apparatus - so that its saliva can be collected and the bell rung (and shocks
given, etc). The dog is reduced to a cartoon of salivation (there
are literally lots of joke cartoons out there concerning conditioned reflexes).
[6]
These diagrams, in turn, form the basis for an even more abstract model, namely
of the conditioned reflex (or even behaviourism). This all begins quite literally - in
direct experienced relations, excluded from the diagrams and models - with the constraining of the real dog
into an apparatus.
Likewise, on the web you
will find striking pictures of the embodied contexts of the communication
model, in what Edwards calls, the soldier or sailor as ‘the machine in the
middle’ (think of sailors strapped into a ship’s gun during the World War II -
these guns used both personnel and other technical aspects of the system to
target and fire in one total assemblage - thus men as the ‘machine in the
middle’).
Dogs in labs, sailors
strapped into guns. These are perhaps ur-models for more contemporary cognitive
times. In all of them, a severe restriction of embodied contexts is then
abstracted - these contexts then become diagrams and form new systems of signs
(new symbolic orders). And these become a means of constraining our behaviour
across a wider set of different behaviours and thinking processes.
As a side note, Pavlov was
himself like the dogs, at least as he had modeled them. Like Kant, he was
extremely repetitive in his daily habits (going to bed at exactly the same time
every day) - until contingency struck in the form of the effects of war, after
which he had insomnia (in which, I can attest personally, radical empiricism
strikes with a vengeance).
Kant’s need of a dog
(suggested music while
reading - Stripped by Depeche Mode)
Dogs figure even earlier,
not only as abstracted figures but as figures of the very possibility of
abstraction itself. We can here head briefly to Kant, where we also find
constrained dogs, in fact dogs that are arguably dead. They are dead because
for Kant they must form a schemata before we can have embodied relation to
them.
David E. Johnson has pointed
to the significance of the dog at a crucial moment in Kant’s Critique of
Pure Reason - perhaps the crucial moment not only of this book, but of whatever it was that
was to become the modern and the West. Johnson doubts that Kant took a dog
along for his famous walks. Yet the dog - as concept - nevertheless accompanies
him ‘at the moment in the Critique of Pure Reason that he determines the
possibility of the conceptualization of sense perception’ (Johnson: 19). Here
time - and therefore contingency, shifting ecologies of relations, perhaps
relations themselves - are subjugated to the search for the structure of the
faculties - the modeling and regulation of cognition.
[7]
As Johnson writes, this is a
key moment in Western philosophy, one that is also foundational for much of
what is modern about modern culture, or to the attempt to conjure up modern
culture through the ritual magic of models. It is a moment that-
Heidegger considered the
very heart of Kant’s critical project and which ultimately turns on the
regulation of the synthesis of time [... at this moment] Kant trots out man’s
best friend. Although he needs this dog in order to demonstrate the trick of temporal
synthesis that makes any sensible conceptuality possible, it is also clear that
he needs to keep this dog on a tight leash; he cannot afford to let it run off
or go astray. On one reading, then, the Critique of Pure Reason institutes a
sort of leash law. Indeed, Kant holds the dog so tightly that it is always
already a dead dog - philosophical road kill. (Johnson: 19)
Why is it necessary for the
dog to be ‘always already a dead dog’? It is again because this enables it to
function as linking a strongly recognisable and everyday set of embodied sense
perceptions (our everyday experience of dogs) to a new and substitute structure
- a model - at an abstract level (reflecting upon our own cognition). This is a structure of
second-order experience that substitutes for more direct experiential relations
while appearing to incorporate them. Kant writes -
The concept of a dog
signifies a rule in accordance with which my imagination can specify the shape
of a four-footed animal in general, without being restricted to any simple
particular shape that experience offers me or any possible image that I can
exhibit in concreto. (in Johnson: 28 -
Kant 182-183)
Although it is intuition -
the passive synthesis of time and space - that is foundational here, in what is
left of ontology for Kant - intuition is, first and foremost, an aspect of
cognitive structure (if one strangely inside and outside of it). One’s
understanding of intuited relations is determined by one’s understanding of
given cognitive structures. So is the understanding of the transformation of
sensed experience into perception.
In short, one’s thinking
processes - or more accurately the
need for a model of thinking processes - become the basis for experience, not
the other way around. To put this slightly differently, one understands one’s
own thinking on the basis of one’s models of thinking processes. Relations,
contingency, time are subjugated to these models. In the process, there seem to
be a lot of dead dogs. It is perhaps interesting in passing to note, there are
also dead ducks, as much later, Norbert Wiener, the founder of cybernetics, saw
the whole problem of cybernetic systems as arising from his experience as a
duck hunter.
[8]
We are all Kantians to some
extent. Cultural practices become more and more about regulating one’s cultural
practice on the basis of cognitive models. Was it therefore wishful thinking
that led James, who first articulated the notion of a radical empiricism, to
write that ‘The true line of philosophic progress lies [...] not so much
through Kant as round him ....’ (in Rockmore: 1).
Rethinking the “Big Think’
(suggested music while
reading - Brian Eno’s How Many Worlds?)
There have been immeasurable
gains from the Kantian cognitive turn, as from Pavlov.
Much, however, has been lost along the way. There is not the
space here to discuss this in any detail, except to mention a few examples. One
would concern the impact of Sigmund Freud’s nephew Edward Bernays, who
martialled cognitive models (including Freud’s) to remake culture in the image
of what he called his own ‘big think’, in PR and spin. Adam Curtis, in his
expansive documentary, The Century of the Self, makes very broad claims for the way
in which Bernays was able to dramatically transform culture into a culture of
consumers whose democratic choice was constrained to a choice between
products.
There are other important
cognitive trials, diagrams and models that have had surprising cultural
effects. Among them is what was
once known as the Hebb-Hayek synaptic learning model. Donald Olding Hebb, a
distinguished neuroscientist who founded the notion of the neural network, was
also the scientist who pioneered research into more constrained behaviours -
this time involving sensory deprivation. It is these experiments that were to
form the model for torture techniques (McCoy - earlier I mentioned Ronell’s
linking of torture and testing). Hayek is of course Friedrich Hayek, Margaret
Thatcher’s favourite economist. Hayek’s model of cognition - outlined in a book
appropriately named The Sensory Order was crucial to his theory of the
market, and thus to neoclassical economics and neoliberalism. All of these
start with constrained/constraining behaviours, whether of dogs, sailors or
even neurons or markets, and extrapolate models from them in something of a cognitive
turn. Via
what Ronell has called the ‘test drive’ and other ritual activities, such as
the implementation of the ‘big think’ by marketing professionals or in productivity
measures,
the cognitive turn becomes the cultural turn.
Although there are of course
important differences between the context and forms involved, many of the forms
of behaviour modification and cognitive compliance are very similar across
these different aspects of the cognitive/cultural turn. And once again much of
this moves against relationality, fidelity to specific and contextual
experience, and in fact, the things that make radical empiricism radical.
Rethinking the Functions of
Science
(suggested music while
reading - Christopher Willits - The Fall in Love Machine)
I
hope the above does not suggest that science in itself is responsible for all
the evils of the world. This is of
course not the case. It is a question, however, of rethinking the relations
between experiment and models.
This is perhaps something that can be gestured toward briefly
via the question of the I hope I I hope the above does not suggest that science
in itself is responsible for all the evils of the world. This is of course not
the case. It is a question, however, of rethinking the relations between
experiment and models.
This is perhaps something
that can be gestured toward briefly via the question of the function, which in
Eric Alliez’ extremely subtle reading of Deleuze and Guattari’s approach to
science, does not abandon the force of embodiment, or at least does not have
to. Earlier, I noted that a defined function in science is, for Deleuze and
Guattari, performative. It involves ‘a fantastic slowing down’ by which
‘matter, as well as the scientific thought able to penetrate it with
propositions, is actualized’ (Deleuze and Guattari, 1994: 118). Alliez takes
this further, suggesting that functions - even functions that, somewhat like
signs, envelop matter in a metric schema (Alliez: 49) - might slow down matter
without abandoning that which ‘draws [this schema] outside itself’. Thinking
this way allows for a ‘definition in tension of the modern power of science, which
sees integrated into its functional practice the force-field that constitutes it’
(Alliez: 49).
This force-field is
precisely that engaged with by radical empiricism. It is the force-field of
real relations, of immanence, of contingency and immediate ecology.
A Very Rough Conclusion -
The Importance of Failure
(suggested music while
reading - Charlotte Gainsbourg - Tel que tu es)
In the face of the ubiquity
of the test drive, and of its many cognitive models and practices, we can
perhaps realise the urgency of a radical empiricism, if only to reintroduce
some
tension within the functions of science.
There are many ways to go
with this. One I will point to here is the importance of accepting failure, of
miscommunication, of boredom, as well as the excitement of experiment, and all
this instead of the mega-organisation of cognitive cultures.
Perhaps also important are
alternative practices and techniques involving thinking processes. In an
article which was one of the first to trigger much of my interest in these
areas, William Connolly (1999) uses brain research itself to begin to fragment
what he was later to call ‘neuropolitics’ (2002). He points to the ‘second
brain’ in the enteric nervous system (the ‘guts’ have neurons just like the
brain - thus ‘gut feelings’). He points to the role that technics play in the
tactics and counter-tactics that work below the threshold of consciousness. He
writes that ‘thinking is irreducible to any of the ingredients that enable it,
but also affected profoundly by the infrasensible media of its occurrence’
(Connolly, 1999:22). In the light of all this, Connolly suggests a ‘list of
techniques, both gross and subtle, by which thinking might be modified in its
course, speed, intensity or sensibility’ (1999: 25). Are such techniques
working for or against the new cognitive orders? I’ll let you decide:
* You go for a run after
having struggled with a paradox of antinomy that perplexes you...
* You expose yourself to an
image that, against your conscious intent, has disturbed you in the past, while
listening to the Talking Heads in the bathtub and imagining how mellow it would
be to dive into crystal blue water off a Caribbean beach...
* You give into a feeling of
intense regret you had previously resisted...
* You go dancing .[...]
(Connolly, 1999: 25)
I will conclude, in a
somewhat inconclusive way, as follows. I will suggest that the diverse world of
cognitive practices, particularly when coupled with the development of computer
media and new social network technologies, provide new means of contact and
cooperation, as well as some of the most pernicious forms of social
organization we have seen. I will suggest that radical empiricism -
research-creation - is part of the solution. However, I will also suggest that
often radical empiricism and, at times, the most constrictive of cognitive
practices, can be very much entangled. I suggested that this can be for better,
or it can be for worse.
In short, radical empiricism
is not an automatic good, but must be made so.
Notes
1. One could see a new domain of contemporary politics opening up here at the level of the emergence of events, one for political research-creation. This is at once the domain in which there is a struggle between preterritorialisation, what Erin Manning has labeled ‘preacceleration’ (2007), the feeling that comes just before an event of movement, and what Bernard Stiegler has called the ‘pseudo a priori’ (2003), a technics that regulates what comes before by reconfiguring it afterwards, as if such things had always been this way (as Stiegler points out, for example, ‘the a priori of synthetic judgment of consciousness takes place after the event’).
2. http://www.collectivate.net/initiatives/free-cooperation-networks-art-collaboration.html, see also Christophe Spehr’s text on Freecooperation at http://www.republicart.net/art/concept/alttransspehr_en.htm (2003), and Scholz and Lovink (2007).
3. See Massumi (2002), DeLanda (2002); the virtual can be variously defined as: the conservation of the past (and in an open sense, the future) in the present; that which exceeds specific forms and processes that are actualized; the network of relations that exceed individuals or individual instances, that is, the network of preindividual reality; the complex structure immanent to any given interaction, which exceeds it, but inheres within it, and makes it possible. As Deleuze puts it, ‘The reality of the virtual is structure. We must avoid giving the elements and relations which form a structure an actuality that they do not have, and withdrawing from them a reality which they have’ (1994:209). Think of a delightful picnic, or a nightmare. Think of the elements and relations which exceed this picnic or nightmare, but from which picnics or nightmares come into being, or more correctly, actualise as durational experience over time. On the virtual and technology see Murphie (2002) and Munster (2006), pp.86ff.
4. See also Stephen Muecke’s Ancient and Modern and José Gil’s Metamorphoses of the Body for more on the effective nature of ritual magic in either the ancient or modern aspects of the world.5. Edwards argues much of the cognitive psychology also derives in part from this communications problem in battle.
6. I am not suggesting that science is incorrect here, of course - only that it amplifies a certain aspect of experience at the expense of the rest.
7. Deleuze writes that ‘Despite the fact that it has become discredited today, the doctrine of the faculties is an entirely necessary component of the system of philosophy’ (1994:143). Thanks to Gary Genosko for this information.
Works Cited
Clark, Andy. Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997.
Connolly, William E. “Brain waves, transcendental fields and techniques of thought” Radical Philosophy 94 (Mar-Apr, 1999). 19-28.
Connolly, William E. Neuropolitics: Thinking, Culture, Speed . Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002.
Cuny, Hilaire. Ivan Pavlov; The Man and his Theories . London: Souvenir Press, 1969.
DeLanda, Manuel. Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy London: Continuum, 2002.
Deleuze, Gilles. The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque . Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993.
Deleuze, Gilles. Difference and Repetition . New York: Columbia University Press, 1994.
Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Félix. A Thousand Plateaus. Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987.
Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Félix. What is Philosophy? New York: Columbia University Press, 1994.
Dupuy, Jean-Pierre. The Mechanization of the Mind: On the Origins of Cognitive Science. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000.
Fancher, Raymond E. Pioneers of Psychology . New York: W. W. Norton, 1979.
Fuller, Matthew. Media Ecologies: Materialist Energies in Art and Technoculture . Cambridge, MA: MIT press, 2005.
Gil, José. Metamorphoses of the Body . Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1998.
Heidegger, Martin. “The Age of the World Picture” in Timothy Druckrey (ed.) Electronic Culture: Technology and Visual Representation . New York: Aperture, 1996. 47-61.
James, William. The Essays in Radical Empiricism. New York: Longman Green, 1912.
Johnston, David E. “Kant's Dog”, Diacritics 34 (2004). 19-39.
Lakoff, George and Johnson, Mark. Philosophy in the Flesh : The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought . New York: HarperCollins, 1999.
Lakoff, George and Johnson, Mark. Metaphors we Live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2003.
Latour, Bruno. “Why Has Critique Run out of Steam? From Matters of Fact to Matter of Concern”, Critical Inquiry 30 (Winter 2004). 225-248.
Manning, Erin. “Incipient Action: The Dance of the Not-Yet”, in Lynn Turner (ed.) Choreographesis . New York: Routledge, forthcoming.
Massumi, Brian. “Involutionary Afterword: Deleuze, Guattari and the Philosophy of Expression” in Canadian Review of Comparative Literature: Review Canadienne de Littérature Comparée 24.3 (1997). 743-782.
Massumi, Brian. Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation . Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2002.
McCoy, Alfred. A Question of Torture : CIA Interrogation, from the Cold War to the War on Terror . New York: Metropolitan, 2006.
Muecke, Stephen. Ancient and Modern: time, culture and indigenous philosophy. Sydney: UNSW Press, 2004.
Munster, Anna. Materializing New Media: Embodiment in Information Aesthetics. Hanover: University Press of New England, 2006.
Munster, Anna and Murphie, Andrew. “Assemblage for Collective Thought”, Aminima 20 (2007).
Murphie, Andrew. “Putting the Virtual Back in to VR” in Brian Massumi (ed.) A Shock to Thought: Expression after Deleuze and Guattari. London: Routledge, 2002. 188-214.
Murphie, Andrew. “ ‘Brain-Magic’: Figures of the Brain, Technology and Magic’”in John Potts and Edward Scheer (eds.) Technologies of Magic . Sydney: Power, 2006. 112-124.
Rockmore, Tom. In Kant's Wake: Philosophy in the Twentieth Century . Oxford: Blackwell, 2006.
Ronell, Avital. The Test Drive. Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 2005.
Scholz, Trebor and Lovink, Geert. The Art of Free Cooperation. New York: Autonomedia/Institute of Distributed Creativity, 2007.
Sokal, Alan and Bricmont, Jean. Intellectual Impostures: Postmodern Philosophers' Abuse of Science. London: Profile, 1998.
Spehr, Christophe. ‘Freecooperation’, republic art, (2003), http://www.republicart.net/art/concept/alttransspehr_en.htm
Stengers, Isabelle. The Invention of Modern Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2000.
Stiegler, Bernard. Technics and Time, 1: The Fault of Epimetheus. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998.
Stiegler, Bernard. ‘Our Ailing Educational Institutions’, Culture Machine 5 (2003), http://culturemachine.tees.ac.uk/Articles/Stiegler.htm
|
|
INFLeXions No. 1 (May 2008)
How is Research-Creation?
NODE:
edited by Alanna Thain
Affective Commotion
Alanna Thain
Creative Propositions for Thought in Motion
Erin Manning
The Thinking-Feeling of What Happens: A Semblance of a Conversation
Brian Massumi
Clone your Technics! Research-Creation, Radical Empiricism and the Constraints of Models
Andrew Murphie
Thinking Spaces for Research-Creation
Derek McCormack
Infinity in a Step: On the Compression and Complexity of a Movement Thought
Stamatia Portanova
TANGENTS:
edited by Christoph Brunner and Natasha Prevost
Systèmes des Sons
Frédéric Lavoie
What is a Smooth Plane? A journey of Nomadology 001
Yuk Hui
Horizons
Amélie Brisson-Darveau
Fugue Marc Ngui: Diagrams for Deleuze & Guattari’s A Thousand Plateaus
Bianca Scliar Mancini
Diagrams for Deleuze & Guattari's A Thousand Plateaus
Marc Ngui
This Was Now; Terrains of Absence
Mark Iwinski |